summaryrefslogtreecommitdiff
path: root/docs/copyright-vs-community.md
blob: 72c984536ea3bdd79bff528bb0ebab7a9f144248 (plain)
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
---
Generator: 'texi2html 1.82'
description: Untitled Document
distribution: global
keywords: Untitled Document
resource-type: document
title: Untitled Document
...

1. Copyright vs. Community\
@entrybreak{}in the Age of Computer Networks {#copyright-vs.-community-entrybreakin-the-age-of-computer-networks .chapter}
============================================

> This is a transcript of the keynote speech presented by Richard
> Stallman, on 12 October 2009, at the LIANZA conference, at the
> Christchurch Convention Centre, in Christchurch, New Zealand.

@firstcopyingnotice{{Copyright © 2009 Free Software Foundation, Inc.\
 Thank you to Bookman for the original transcript. This version of it is
part of @fsfsthreecite}

> **Brenda Chawner:** Tena koutou, tena koutou, tena koutou katoa. Today
> I have the privilege of introducing Richard Stallman, whose keynote
> speech is being sponsored by the School of Information Management at
> Victoria University of Wellington.
>
> Richard has been working to promote software freedom for over 25
> years. In 1983 he started the GNU Project to develop a free operating
> system \[the GNU system\], and in 1985 he set up the Free Software
> Foundation. Every time you read or send a message to nz-libs, you use
> the Mailman software which is part of the GNU Project. So whether you
> realize it or not, Richard’s work has touched all of your lives.
>
> I like to describe him as the most influential person most people have
> never heard of, although he tells me that that cannot possibly be true
> because it cannot be tested.
>
> **RMS:** We can’t tell.
>
> **BC:** I said that—I still like it. His ideas about software freedom
> and free access to information were used by Tim Berners-Lee when he
> created the world’s first web server, and in 1999 his musings about a
> free online encyclopedia inspired Jimmy Wales to set up what is now
> Wikipedia.
>
> Today Richard will be talking to us about copyright vs. community in
> the age of computer networks, and their implications for libraries.
> Richard.
>
> **RMS:** I’ve been in New Zealand for a couple of weeks, and in the
> North Island it was raining most of the time. Now I know why they call
> gumboots “Wellingtons.” And then I saw somebody who was making chairs
> and tables out of ponga wood, and he called it fern-iture. Then we
> took the ferry to get here, and as soon as we got off, people started
> mocking and insulting us; but there were no hard feelings, they just
> wanted to make us really feel Picton.

The reason people usually invite me to give speeches is because of my
work on free software. This is not a talk about free software; this talk
answers the question whether the ideas of free software extend to other
kinds of works. But in order for that to make sense, I’d better tell you
briefly what free software means.

Free software is a matter of freedom, not price, so think of “free
speech,” not “free beer.” Free software is software that respects the
user’s freedom, and there are four specific freedoms that the user
deserves always to have:

-   Freedom 0 is the freedom to run the program as you wish.
-   Freedom 1 is the freedom to study the source code of the program and
    change it to make the program do what you wish.
-   Freedom 2 is the freedom to help your neighbor—that is, the freedom
    to redistribute copies of the program, exact copies when you wish.
-   And freedom 3 is the freedom to contribute to your community. That’s
    the freedom to publish your modified versions when you wish.

If the program gives you these four freedoms then it’s free software,
which means the social system of its distribution and use is an ethical
system, one which respects the user’s freedom and the social solidarity
of the user’s community. But if one of these freedoms is missing or
insufficient, then it’s proprietary software, nonfree software,
user-subjugating software. It’s unethical. It’s not a contribution to
society. It’s a power grab. This unethical practice should not exist;
the goal of the free software movement is to put an end to it. All
software should be free, so that all users can be free.

Proprietary software keeps the users divided and helpless: divided,
because they’re forbidden to share it, and helpless, because they don’t
have the source code so they can’t change it. They can’t even study it
to verify what it’s really doing to them, and many proprietary programs
have malicious features which spy on the user, restrict the user, even
back doors to attack the user.

For instance, Microsoft Windows has a back door with which Microsoft can
forcibly install software changes, without getting permission from the
supposed owner of the computer. You may think it’s your computer, but if
you’ve made the mistake of having Windows running in it, then really
Microsoft has owned your computer. Computers need to be defenestrated,
which means either throw Windows out of the computer, or throw the
computer out the window.

But any proprietary software gives the developers unjust power over the
users. Some of the developers abuse this power more, and some abuse it
less, but none of them ought to have it. You deserve to have control of
your computing, and not be forcibly dependent on a particular company.
So you deserve free software.

At the end of speeches about free software, people sometimes ask whether
these same freedoms and ideas apply to other things. If you have a copy
of a published work on your computer, it makes sense to ask whether you
should have the same four freedoms—whether it’s ethically essential that
you have them or not. And that’s the question that I’m going to address
today.

If you have a copy of something that’s not software, for the most part,
the only thing that might deny you any of these freedoms is copyright
law. With software that’s not so. The main ways of making software
nonfree are contracts and withholding the source code from the users.
Copyright is a sort of secondary, back up method. For other things
there’s no such distinction as between source code and executable code.

For instance, if we’re talking about a text, if you can see the text to
read it, there’s nothing in the text that you can’t see. So it’s not the
same kind of issue exactly as software. It’s for the most part only
copyright that might deny you these freedoms.

So the question can be restated: “What should copyright law allow you to
do with published works? What should copyright law say?”

Copyright has developed along with copying technology, so it’s useful to
review the history of copying technology. Copying developed in the
ancient world, where you’d use a writing instrument on a writing
surface. You’d read one copy and write another.

This technology was rather inefficient, but another interesting
characteristic was that it had no economy of scale. To write ten copies
would take ten times as long as to write one copy. It required no
special equipment other than the equipment for writing, and it required
no special skill other than literacy itself. The result was that copies
of any particular book were made in a decentralized manner. Wherever
there was a copy, if someone wanted to copy it, he could.

There was nothing like copyright in the ancient world. If you had a copy
and wanted to copy it, nobody was going to tell you you weren’t
allowed—except if the local prince didn’t like what the book said, in
which case he might punish you for copying it. But that’s not copyright,
but rather something closely related, namely censorship. To this day,
copyright is often used in attempts to censor people.

That went on for thousands of years, but then there was a big advance in
copying technology, namely the printing press. The printing press made
copying more efficient, but not uniformly. \[This was\] because mass
production copying became a lot more efficient, but making one copy at a
time didn’t benefit from the printing press. In fact, you were better
off just writing it by hand; that would be faster than trying to print
one copy.

The printing press has an economy of scale: it takes a lot of work to
set the type, but then you can make many copies very fast. Also, the
printing press and the type were expensive equipment that most people
didn’t own; and the ability to use them, most literate people didn’t
know. Using a press was a different skill from writing. The result was a
centralized manner of producing copies: the copies of any given book
would be made in a few places, and then they would be transported to
wherever someone wanted to buy copies.

Copyright began in the age of the printing press. Copyright in England
began as a system of censorship in the 1500s. I believe it was
originally meant to censor Protestants, but it was turned around and
used to censor Catholics and presumably lots of others as well.
According to this law, in order to publish a book you had to get
permission from the Crown, and this permission was granted in the form
of a perpetual monopoly to publish it. This was allowed to lapse in the
1680s, I believe \[it expired in 1695 according to the Wikipedia
entry\]. The publishers wanted it back again, but what they got was
something somewhat different. The Statute of Anne gave authors a
copyright, and only for 14 years, although the author could renew it
once.

This was a totally different idea—a temporary monopoly for the author,
instead of a perpetual monopoly for the publisher. The idea developed
that copyright was a means of promoting writing.

When the US constitution was written, some people wanted authors to be
entitled to a copyright, but that was rejected. Instead, the US
Constitution says that Congress can optionally adopt a copyright law,
and if there is a copyright law, its purpose is to promote progress. In
other words, the purpose is not benefits for copyright holders or
anybody they do business with, but for the general public. Copyright has
to last a limited time; publishers keep hoping for us to forget about
this.

Here we have an idea of copyright which is an industrial regulation on
publishers, controlled by authors, and designed to provide benefits to
the public at large. It functioned this way because it didn’t restrict
the readers.

Now in the early centuries of printing, and still I believe in the
1790s, lots of readers wrote copies by hand because they couldn’t afford
printed copies. Nobody ever expected copyright law to be something other
than an industrial regulation. It wasn’t meant to stop people from
writing copies, it was meant to regulate the publishers. Because of this
it was easy to enforce, uncontroversial, and arguably beneficial for
society.

It was easy to enforce, because it only had to be enforced against
publishers. And it’s easy to find the unauthorized publishers of a
book—you go to a bookstore and say, “Where do these copies come from?”
You don’t have to invade everybody’s home and everybody’s computer to do
that.

It was uncontroversial because, as the readers were not restricted, they
had nothing to complain about. Theoretically they were restricted from
publishing, but not being publishers and not having printing presses,
they couldn’t do that anyway. In what they actually could do, they were
not restricted.

It was arguably beneficial because the general public, according to the
concepts of copyright law, traded away a theoretical right they were not
in a position to exercise. In exchange, they got the benefits of more
writing.

Now if you trade away something you have no possible use for, and you
get something you can use in exchange, it’s a positive trade. Whether or
not you could have gotten a better deal some other way, that’s a
different question, but at least it’s positive.

So if this were still in the age of the printing press, I don’t think
I’d be complaining about copyright law. But the age of the printing
press is gradually giving way to the age of the computer
networks—another advance in copying technology that makes copying more
efficient, and once again not uniformly so.

Here’s what we had in the age of the printing press: mass production
very efficient, one at a time copying still just as slow as the ancient
world. Digital technology gets us here: they’ve both benefited, but
one-off copying has benefited the most.

We get to a situation much more like the ancient world, where one at a
time copying is not so much worse \[i.e., harder\] than mass production
copying. It’s a little bit less efficient, a little bit less good, but
it’s perfectly cheap enough that hundreds of millions of people do it.
Consider how many people write CDs once in a while, even in poor
countries. You may not have a CD-writer yourself, so you go to a store
where you can do it.

This means that copyright no longer fits in with the technology as it
used to. Even if the words of copyright law had not changed, they
wouldn’t have the same effect. Instead of an industrial regulation on
publishers controlled by authors, with the benefits set up to go to the
public, it is now a restriction on the general public, controlled mainly
by the publishers, in the name of the authors.

In other words, it’s tyranny. It’s intolerable and we can’t allow it to
continue this way.

As a result of this change, \[copyright\] is no longer easy to enforce,
no longer uncontroversial, and no longer beneficial.

It’s no longer easy to enforce because now the publishers want to
enforce it against each and every person, and to do this requires cruel
measures, draconian punishments, invasions of privacy, abolition of our
basic ideas of justice. There’s almost no limit to how far they will
propose to go to prosecute the War on Sharing.

It’s no longer uncontroversial. There are political parties in several
countries whose basic platform is “freedom to share.”

It’s no longer beneficial because the freedoms that we conceptually
traded away (because we couldn’t exercise them), we now can exercise.
They’re tremendously useful, and we want to exercise them.

What would a democratic government do in this situation?

It would reduce copyright power. It would say: “The trade we made on
behalf of our citizens, trading away some of their freedom which now
they need, is intolerable. We have to change this; we can’t trade away
the freedom that is important.” We can measure the sickness of democracy
by the tendency of governments to do the exact opposite around the
world, extending copyright power when they should reduce it.

One example is in the dimension of time. Around the world we see
pressure to make copyright last longer and longer and longer.

A wave of this started in the US in 1998. Copyright was extended by 20
years on both past and future works. I do not understand how they hope
to convince the now dead or senile writers of the 20s and 30s to write
more back then by extending copyright on their works now. If they have a
time machine with which to inform them, they haven’t used it. Our
history books don’t say that there was a burst of vigor in the arts in
the 20s when all the artists found out that their copyrights would be
extended in 1998.

It’s theoretically conceivable that 20 years more copyright on future
works would convince people to make more effort in producing those
works. But not anyone rational, because the discounted present value of
20 more years of copyright starting 75 years in the future—if it’s a
work made for hire—and probably even longer if it’s a work with an
individual copyright holder, is so small it couldn’t persuade any
rational person to do anything different. Any business that wants to
claim otherwise ought to present its projected balance sheets for 75
years in the future, which of course they can’t do because none of them
really looks that far ahead.

The real reason for this law, the desire that prompted various companies
to purchase this law in the US Congress, which is how laws are decided
on for the most part, was they had lucrative monopolies and they wanted
those monopolies to continue.

For instance, Disney was aware that the first film in which Mickey Mouse
appeared would go into the public domain in a few years, and then
anybody would be free to draw that same character as part of other
works. Disney didn’t want that to happen. Disney borrows a lot from the
public domain, but is determined never to give the slightest thing back.
So Disney paid for this law, which we refer to as the Mickey Mouse
Copyright Act.

The movie companies say they want perpetual copyright, but the US
Constitution won’t let them get that officially. So they came up with a
way to get the same result unofficially: “perpetual copyright on the
installment plan.” Every 20 years they extend copyright for 20 more
years. So that at any given time, any given work has a date when it will
supposedly fall into the public domain. But that date is like tomorrow,
it never comes. By the time you get there they will have postponed it,
unless we stop them next time.

That’s one dimension, the dimension of duration. But even more important
is the dimension of breadth: which uses of the work does copyright
cover?

In the age of the printing press, copyright wasn’t supposed to cover all
uses of a copyrighted work, because copyright regulated certain uses
that were the exceptions in a broader space of unregulated uses. There
were certain things you were simply allowed to do with your copy of a
book.

Now the publishers have got the idea that they can turn our computers
against us, and use them to seize total power over all use of published
works. They want to set up a pay-per-view universe. They’re doing it
with DRM (Digital Restrictions Management)—the intentional features of
software that’s designed to restrict the user. And often the computer
itself is designed to restrict the user.

The first way in which the general public saw this was in DVDs. A movie
on a DVD was usually encrypted, and the format was secret. The DVD
conspiracy kept this secret because they said anyone that wants to make
DVD players has to join the conspiracy, promise to keep the format
secret, and promise to design the DVD players to restrict the users
according to the rules, which say it has to stop the user from doing
this, from doing that, from doing that—a precise set of requirements,
all of which are malicious towards us.

It worked for a while, but then some people figured out the secret
format, and published free software capable of reading the movie on a
DVD and playing it. Then the publishers said, “Since we can’t actually
stop them, we have to make it a crime.” And they started that in the US
in 1998 with the Digital Millennium Copyright Act, which imposed
censorship on software capable of doing such jobs.

So that particular piece of free software was the subject of a court
case. Its distribution in the US is forbidden; the US practices
censorship of software.

The movie companies are well aware that they can’t really make that
program disappear—it’s easy enough to find it. So they designed another
encryption system, which they hoped would be harder to break, and it’s
called AACS, or the axe.

The AACS conspiracy makes precise rules about all players. For instance,
in 2011 it’s going to be forbidden to make analog video outputs. So all
video outputs will have to be digital, and they will carry the signal
encrypted into a monitor specially designed to keep secrets from the
user. That is malicious hardware. They say that the purpose of this is
to “close the analog hole.” *\[Stallman takes off his glasses.\]* Here’s
one and here’s another, that they’d like to poke out
permanently.[(1)](#FOOT1)

How do I know about these conspiracies? The reason is they’re not
secret—they have web sites. The AACS web site proudly describes the
contracts that manufacturers have to sign, which is how I know about
this requirement. It proudly states the names of the companies that have
established this conspiracy, which include Microsoft and Apple, and
Intel, and Sony, and Disney, and IBM.

A conspiracy of companies designed to restrict the public’s access to
technology ought to be prosecuted as a serious crime, like a conspiracy
to fix prices, except it’s worse, so the prison sentences for this
should be longer. But these companies are quite confident that our
governments are on their side against us. They have no fear against
being prosecuted for these conspiracies, which is why they don’t bother
to hide them.

In general, DRM is set up by a conspiracy of companies. Once in a while
a single company can do it, but generally it requires a conspiracy
between technology companies and publishers, so \[it’s\] almost always a
conspiracy.

They thought that nobody would ever be able to break the AACS, but about
three and a half years ago someone released a free program capable of
decrypting that format. However, it was totally useless, because in
order to run it you need to know the key.

And then, six months later, I saw a photo of two adorable puppies, with
32 hex digits above them, and I wondered, “Why put those two things
together? I wonder if those numbers are some important key, and someone
could have put the numbers together with the puppies, figuring people
would copy the photo of the puppies because they were so cute. This
would protect the key from being wiped out.”

And that’s what it was—that was the key to break the axe. People posted
it, and editors deleted it, because laws in many countries now conscript
them to censor this information. It was posted again, they deleted it;
eventually they gave up, and in two weeks this number was posted in over
700,000 web sites.

That’s a big outpouring of public disgust with DRM. But it didn’t win
the war, because the publishers changed the key. Not only that: with HD
DVD, this was adequate to break the DRM, but not with Blu-ray. Blu-ray
has an additional level of DRM and so far there is no free software that
can break it, which means that you must regard Blu-ray disks as
something incompatible with your own freedom. They are an enemy with
which no accommodation is possible, at least not with our present level
of knowledge.

Never accept any product designed to attack your freedom. If you don’t
have the free software to play a DVD, you mustn’t buy or rent any DVDs,
or accept them even as gifts, except for the rare non-encrypted DVDs,
which there are a few of. I actually have a few \[of these\]—I don’t
have any encrypted DVDs, I won’t take them.

So this is how things stand in video, but we’ve also seen DRM in music.

For instance, about ten years ago we started to see things that looked
like compact disks, but they weren’t written quite like compact disks.
They didn’t follow the standard. We called them “corrupt disks,” and the
idea of them was that they would play in an audio player, but it was
impossible to read them on a computer. These different methods had
various problems.

Eventually Sony came up with a clever idea. They put a program on the
disk, so that if you stuck the disk into a computer, the disk would
install the program. This program was designed like a virus to take
control of the system. It’s called a “root kit,” meaning that it has
things in it to break the security of the system so that it can install
the software deep inside the system, and modify various parts of the
system.

For instance, it modified the command you could use to examine the
system to see if the software was present, so as to disguise itself. It
modified the command you could use to delete some of these files, so
that it wouldn’t really delete them. Now all of this is a serious crime,
but it’s not the only one Sony committed, because the software also
included free software code—code that had been released under the GNU
General Public License.

Now the GNU GPL is a copyleft license, and that means it says, “Yes,
you’re free to put this code into other things, but when you do, the
entire program that you put things into you must release as free
software under the same license. And you must make the source code
available to users, and to inform them of their rights you must give
them a copy of this license when they get the software.”

Sony didn’t comply with all that. That’s commercial copyright
infringement, which is a felony. They’re both felonies, but Sony wasn’t
prosecuted because the government understands that the purpose of the
government and the law is to maintain the power of those companies over
us, not to help defend our freedom in any way.

People got angry and they sued Sony. However, they made a mistake. They
focused their condemnation not on the evil purpose of this scheme, but
only on the secondary evils of the various methods that Sony used. So
Sony settled the lawsuits and promised that in the future, when it
attacks our freedom, it will not do those other things.

Actually, that particular corrupt disk scheme was not so bad, because if
you were not using Windows it would not affect you at all. Even if you
were using Windows, there’s a key on the keyboard—if you remembered
every time to hold it down, then the disk wouldn’t install the software.
But of course it’s hard to remember that every time; you’re going to
slip up some day. This shows the kind of thing we’ve had to deal with.

Fortunately music DRM is receding. Even the main record companies sell
downloads without DRM. But we see a renewed effort to impose DRM on
books.

You see, the publishers want to take away the traditional freedoms of
book readers—freedom to do things such as borrow a book from the public
library, or lend it to a friend; to sell a book to a used book store, or
buy it anonymously paying cash (which is the only way I buy books—we’ve
got to resist the temptations to let Big Brother know everything that
we’re doing.)

Even the freedom to keep the book as long as you wish, and read it as
many times as you wish, they plan to get rid of.

The way they do it is with DRM. They knew that so many people read books
and would get angry if these freedoms were taken away that they didn’t
believe they could buy a law specifically to abolish these
freedoms—there would be too much opposition. Democracy is sick, but once
in a while people manage to demand something. So they came up with a
two-stage plan.

First, take away these freedoms from e-books, and second, convince
people to switch from paper books to e-books. They’ve succeeded with
stage 1.

In the US they did it with the Digital Millennium Copyright Act, and in
New Zealand, that was part of the Copyright Act \[of 2008\]; censorship
on software that can break DRM was part of that law. That’s an unjust
provision; it’s got to be repealed.

The second stage is convince people to switch from printed books to
e-books; that didn’t go so well.

One publisher in 2001 had the idea they would make their line of e-books
really popular if they started it with my biography. So they found an
author and the author asked me if I’d cooperate, and I said, “Only if
this e-book is published without encryption, without DRM.” The publisher
wouldn’t go along with that, and I just stuck to it—I said no.
Eventually we found another publisher who was willing to do this—in fact
willing to publish the book under a free license giving you the four
freedoms—so the book was then published, and sold a lot of copies on
paper.

But in any case, e-books failed at the beginning of this decade. People
just didn’t want to read them very much. And I said, “They will try
again.” We saw an amazing number of news articles about electronic ink
(or is it electronic paper, I can never remember which), and it occurred
to me probably the reason there’s so many is the publishers want us to
think about this. They want us to be eager for the next generation of
e-book readers.

Now they’re upon us. Things like the Sony Shreader (its official name is
the Sony Reader, but if you put on ‘sh’ it explains what it’s designed
to do to your books), and the Amazon Swindle, designed to swindle you
out of your traditional freedoms without your noticing. Of course, they
call it the Kindle which is what it’s going to do to your books.

The Kindle is an extremely malicious product, almost as malicious as
Microsoft Windows. They both have spy features, they both have Digital
Restrictions Management, and they both have back doors.

In the case of the Kindle, the only way you can buy a book is to buy it
from Amazon, and Amazon requires you to identify yourself, so they know
everything that you’ve bought.

Then there is Digital Restrictions Management, so you can’t lend the
book or sell it to a used bookstore, and the library can’t lend it
either.

And then there’s the back door, which we found out about about three
months ago, because Amazon used it. Amazon sent a command to all the
Kindles to erase a particular book, namely 1984, by George Orwell. Yes,
they couldn’t have picked a more ironic book to erase. So that’s how we
know that Amazon has a back door with which it can erase books remotely.

What else it can do, who knows? Maybe it’s like Microsoft Windows. Maybe
Amazon can remotely upgrade the software, which means that whatever
malicious things are not in it now, they could put them in it tomorrow.

This is intolerable—any one of these restrictions is intolerable. They
want to create a world where nobody lends books to anybody anymore.

Imagine that you visit a friend and there are no books on the shelf.
It’s not that your friend doesn’t read, but his books are all inside a
device, and of course he can’t lend you those books. The only way he
could lend you any one of those books is to lend you his whole library,
which is obviously a ridiculous thing to ask anybody to do. So there
goes friendship for people who love books.

Make sure that you inform people what this device implies. It means
other readers will no longer be your friends, because you will be acting
like a jerk toward them. Spread the word preemptively. This device is
your enemy. It’s the enemy of everyone who reads. The people who don’t
recognize that are the people who are thinking so short-term that they
don’t see it. It’s our job to help them see beyond the momentary
convenience to the implications of this device.

I have nothing against distributing books in digital form, if they are
not designed to take away our freedom. Strictly speaking, it is possible
to have an e-book reader:

-   that is not designed to attack you,
-   which runs free software and not proprietary software,
-   which doesn’t have DRM,
-   which doesn’t make people identify yourself to get a book,
-   which doesn’t have a back door, \[and\]
-   which doesn’t restrict what you can do with the files on
    your machine.

It’s possible, but the big companies really pushing e-books are doing it
to attack our freedom, and we mustn’t stand for that. This is what
governments are doing in cahoots with big business to attack our
freedom, by making copyright harsher and nastier, more restrictive than
ever before.

But what should they do? Governments should make copyright power less.
Here are my specific proposals.

First of all, there is the dimension of time. I propose copyright should
last ten years, starting from the date of publication of a work.

Why from the date of publication? Because before that, we don’t have
copies. It doesn’t matter to us whether we would have been allowed to
copy our copies that we don’t have, so I figure we might as well let the
authors have as much time as it takes to arrange publication, and then
start the clock.

But why ten years? I don’t know about in this country, but in the US,
the publication cycle has got shorter and shorter. Nowadays almost all
books are remaindered within two years and out-of-print within three. So
ten years is more than three times the usual publication cycle—that
should be plenty comfortable.

But not everybody agrees. I once proposed this in a panel discussion
with fiction writers, and the award-winning fantasy writer next to me
said, “Ten years? No way. Anything more than five years is intolerable.”
You see, he had a legal dispute with his publisher. His books seemed to
be out of print, but the publisher wouldn’t admit it. The publisher was
using the copyright on his own book to stop him from distributing copies
himself, which he wanted to do so people could read it.

This is what every artist starts out wanting—wanting to distribute her
work so it will get read and appreciated. Very few make a lot of money.
That tiny fraction face the danger of being morally corrupted, like JK
Rowling.

JK Rowling, in Canada, got an injunction against people who had bought
her book in a bookstore, ordering them not to read it. So in response I
call for a boycott of Harry Potter books. But I don’t say you shouldn’t
read them; I leave that to the author and the publisher. I just say you
shouldn’t buy them.

It’s few authors that make enough money that they can be corrupted in
this way. Most of them don’t get anywhere near that, and continue
wanting the same thing they wanted at the outset: they want their work
to be appreciated.

He wanted to distribute his own book, and copyright was stopping him. He
realized that more than five years of copyright was unlikely to ever do
him any good.

If people would rather have copyright last five years, I won’t be
against it. I propose ten as a first stab at the problem. Let’s reduce
it to ten years and then take stock for a while, and we could adjust it
after that. I don’t say I think ten years is the exact right number—I
don’t know.

What about the dimension of breadth? Which activities should copyright
cover? I distinguish three broad categories of works.

First of all, there are the functional works that you use to do a
practical job in your life. This includes software, recipes, educational
works, reference works, text fonts, and other things you can think of.
These works should be free.

If you use the work to do a job in your life, then if you can’t change
the work to suit you, you don’t control your life. Once you have changed
the work to suit you, then you’ve got to be free to publish it—publish
your version—because there will be others who will want the changes
you’ve made.

This leads quickly to the conclusion that users have to have the same
four freedoms \[for all functional works\], not just for software. And
you’ll notice that for recipes, practically speaking, cooks are always
sharing and changing recipes just as if the recipes were free. Imagine
how people would react if the government tried to stamp out so-called
recipe piracy.

The term “pirate” is pure propaganda. When people ask me what I think of
music piracy, I say, “As far as I know, when pirates attack they don’t
do it by playing instruments badly, they do it with arms. So it’s not
music ‘piracy,’ because piracy is attacking ships, and sharing is as far
as you get from being the moral equivalent of attacking ships.”
Attacking ships is bad, sharing with other people is good, so we should
firmly denounce that propaganda term “piracy” whenever we hear it.

People might have objected twenty years ago: “If we don’t give up our
freedom, if we don’t let the publishers of these works control us, the
works won’t get made and that will be a horrible disaster.” Now, looking
at the free software community, and all the recipes that circulate, and
reference works like Wikipedia—we are even starting to see free
textbooks being published—we know that that fear is misguided.

There is no need to despair and give up our freedom thinking that
otherwise the works won’t get made. There are lots of ways to encourage
them to get made if we want more—lots of ways that are consistent with
and respect our freedom. In this category, they should all be free.

But what about the second category, of works that say what certain
people thought, like memoirs, essays of opinion, scientific
papers,[(2)](#FOOT2) and various other things? To publish a modified
version of somebody else’s statement of what he thought is
misrepresenting \[that\] somebody. That’s not particularly a
contribution to society.

Therefore it is workable and acceptable to have a somewhat reduced
copyright system where all commercial use is covered by copyright, all
modification is covered by copyright, but everyone is free to
non-commercially redistribute exact copies.

That freedom is the minimum freedom we must establish for all published
works, because the denial of that freedom is what creates the War on
Sharing—what creates the vicious propaganda that sharing is theft, that
sharing is like being a pirate and attacking ships. Absurdities, but
absurdities backed by a lot of money that has corrupted our governments.
We need to end the War on Sharing; we need to legalize sharing exact
copies of any published work.

In the second category of works, that’s all we need; we don’t need to
make them free. Therefore I think it’s OK to have a reduced copyright
system which covers commercial use and all modifications. And this will
provide a revenue stream to the authors in more or less the same
(usually inadequate) way as the present system. You’ve got to keep in
mind \[that\] the present system, except for superstars, is usually
totally inadequate.

What about works of art and entertainment? Here it took me a while to
decide what to think about modifications.

You see, on one hand, a work of art can have an artistic integrity and
modifying it could destroy that. Of course, copyright doesn’t
necessarily stop works from being butchered that way. Hollywood does it
all the time. On the other hand, modifying the work can be a
contribution to art. It makes possible the folk process which leads to
things which are beautiful and rich.

Even if we look at named authors only: consider Shakespeare, who
borrowed stories from other works only a few decades old, and did them
in different ways, and made important works of literature. If today’s
copyright law had existed then, that would have been forbidden and those
plays wouldn’t have been written.

But eventually I realized that modifying a work of art can be a
contribution to art, but it’s not desperately urgent in most cases. If
you had to wait ten years for the copyright to expire, you could wait
that long. Not like the present-day copyright that makes you wait maybe
75 years, or 95 years. In Mexico you might have to wait almost 200 years
in some cases, because copyright in Mexico expires a hundred years after
the author dies. This is insane, but ten years, as I’ve proposed
copyright should last, that people can wait.

So I propose the same partly reduced copyright that covers commercial
use and modification, but everyone’s got to be free to non-commercially
redistribute exact copies. After ten years it goes into the public
domain, and people can contribute to art by publishing their modified
versions.

One other thing: if you’re going to take little pieces out of a bunch of
works and rearrange them into something totally different, that should
just be legal, because the purpose of copyright is to promote art, not
to obstruct art. It’s stupid to apply copyright to using snippets like
that—it’s self-defeating. It’s a kind of distortion that you’d only get
when the government is under the control of the publishers of the
existing successful works, and has totally lost sight of its intended
purpose.

That’s what I propose, and in particular, this means that sharing copies
on the internet must be legal. Sharing is good. Sharing builds the bonds
of society. To attack sharing is to attack society.

So any time the government proposes some new means to attack people who
share, to stop them from sharing, we have to recognize that this is
evil, not just because the means proposed almost invariably offend basic
ideas of justice. But that’s not a coincidence; the reason is because
the purpose is evil. Sharing is good and the government should encourage
sharing.

But copyright did after all have a useful purpose. Copyright as a means
to carry out that purpose has a problem now, because it doesn’t fit in
with the technology we use. It interferes with all the vital freedoms
for all the readers, listeners, viewers, and whatever, but the goal of
promoting the arts is still desirable. So in addition to the partly
reduced copyright system, which would continue to be a copyright system,
I propose two other methods.

One \[works via\] taxes—distribute tax money directly to artists. This
could be a special tax, perhaps on internet connectivity, or it could
come from general revenue, because it won’t be that much money in total,
not if it’s distributed in an efficient way. To distribute it
efficiently to promote the arts means not in linear proportion to
popularity. It should be based on popularity, because we don’t want
bureaucrats to have the discretion to decide which artists to support
and which to ignore, but based on popularity does not imply linear
proportion.

What I propose is measure the popularity of the various artists, which
you could do through polling (samples) in which nobody is required to
participate, and then take the cube root. The cube root looks like this:
it means basically that \[the payment\] tapers off after a while.

If superstar A is a thousand times as popular as successful artist B,
with this system A would get ten times as much money as B, not a
thousand times.

Linearly would give A a thousand times as much as B, which means that if
we wanted B to get enough to live on we’re going to have to make A
tremendously rich. This is wasteful use of the tax money—it shouldn’t be
done.

But if we make it taper off, then yes, each superstar will get
handsomely more than an ordinary successful artist, but the total of all
the superstars will be a small fraction of the \[total\] money. Most of
the money will go to support a large number of fairly successful
artists, fairly appreciated artists, fairly popular artists. Thus the
system will use money a lot more efficiently than the existing system.

The existing system is regressive. It actually gives far, far more per
record, for instance, to a superstar than to anybody else. The money is
extremely badly used. The result is we’d actually be paying a lot less
this way. I hope that’s enough to mollify some of these people who have
a knee-jerk hostile reaction to taxes—one that I don’t share, because I
believe in a welfare state.

I have another suggestion which is voluntary payments. Suppose every
player had a button you could push to send a dollar to the artist who
made the work you’re currently playing or the last one you played. This
money would be delivered anonymously to those artists. I think a lot of
people would push that button fairly often.

For instance, all of us could afford to push that button once every day,
and we wouldn’t miss that much money. It’s not that much money for us,
I’m pretty sure. Of course, there are poor people who couldn’t afford to
push it ever, and it’s OK if they don’t. We don’t need to squeeze money
out of poor people to support the artists. There are enough people who
are not poor to do the job just fine. I’m sure you’re aware that a lot
of people really love certain art and are really happy to support the
artists.

An idea just came to me. The player could also give you a certificate of
having supported so-and-so, and it could even count up how many times
you had done it and give you a certificate that says, “I sent so much to
these artists.” There are various ways we could encourage people who
want to do it.

For instance, we could have a PR campaign which is friendly and kind:
“Have you sent a dollar to some artists today? Why not? It’s only a
dollar—you’ll never miss it and don’t you love what they’re doing? Push
the button!” It will make people feel good, and they’ll think, “Yeah, I
love what I just watched. I’ll send a dollar.”

This is already starting to work to some extent. There’s a Canadian
singer who used to be called Jane Siberry. She put her music on her web
site and invited people to download it and pay whatever amount they
wished. She reported getting an average of more than a dollar per copy,
which is interesting because the major record companies charge just
under a dollar per copy. By letting people decide whether and how much
to pay, she got more—she got even more per visitor who was actually
downloading something. But this might not even count whether there was
an effect of bringing more people to come, and \[thus\] increasing the
total number that this average was against.

So it can work, but it’s a pain in the neck under present circumstances.
You’ve got to have a credit card to do it, and that means you can’t do
it anonymously. And you’ve got to go find where you’re going to pay, and
the payment systems for small amounts, they’re not very efficient, so
the artists are only getting half of it. If we set up a good system for
this, it would work far, far better. So these are my two suggestions.

And in [mecenat-global.org](mecenat-global.org),[(3)](#FOOT3) you can
find another scheme that combines aspects of the two, which was invented
by Francis Muguet and designed to fit in with existing legal systems
better to make it easier to enact.

Be careful of proposals to “compensate the rights holders,” because when
they say “compensate,” they’re trying to presume that if you have
appreciated a work, you now have a specific debt to somebody, and that
you have to “compensate” that somebody. When they say “rights holders,”
it’s supposed to make you think it’s supporting artists while in fact
it’s going to the publishers—the same publishers who basically exploit
all the artists (except the few that you’ve all heard of, who are so
popular that they have clout).

We don’t owe a debt; we have nobody that we have to “compensate.”
\[But\] supporting the arts is still a useful thing to do. That was the
motivation for copyright back when copyright fit in with the technology
of the day. Today copyright is a bad way to do it, but it’s still good
to do it other ways that respect our freedom.

Demand that they change the two evil parts of the New Zealand Copyright
Act. They shouldn’t replace the three strikes punishment,[(4)](#FOOT4)
because sharing is good, and they’ve got to get rid of the censorship
for the software to break DRM. Beware of ACTA—they’re trying to
negotiate a treaty between various countries, for all of these countries
to attack their citizens, and we don’t know how because they won’t tell
us.

<div class="footnote">

------------------------------------------------------------------------

### Footnotes

### [(1)](#DOCF1)

@raggedright In 2010, the encryption system for digital video output was
definitively cracked. (See Mark Hachman’s “HDCP Master Key Confirmed;
Blu-Ray Content Vulnerable” (September 16 2010), at
<http://pcmag.com/article2/0,2817,2369280,00.asp>, for more
information.) @end raggedright

### [(2)](#DOCF2)

@raggedright 2015: I included scientific papers because I thought that
publishing modified versions of someone else’s paper would cause harm;
however, publishing physics and math papers under the Creative Commons
Attribution License on [arXiv.org](arXiv.org) and many libre journals
seems to have no problems. Thus, I subsequently concluded that
scientific papers ought to be free. @end raggedright

### [(3)](#DOCF3)

@raggedright That page is no longer active; please see
[https://stallman.org/mecenat/\
global-patronage.html](https://stallman.org/mecenat/%3Cbr%3Eglobal-patronage.html)
instead. @end raggedright

### [(4)](#DOCF4)

@raggedright New Zealand had enacted a system of punishment without
trial for internet users accused of copying; then, facing popular
protest, the government did not implement it, and announced a plan to
implement a modified unjust punishment system. The point here was that
they should not proceed to implement a replacement—rather, they should
have no such system. However, the words I used don’t say this clearly.

@hglue@defaultparindent The New Zealand government subsequently
implemented the punishment scheme more or less as originally planned.
@end raggedright

</div>

------------------------------------------------------------------------

This document was generated by *tonghuix* on *March 25, 2016* using
[*texi2html 1.82*](http://www.nongnu.org/texi2html/).\